Arthadhigama Chintan

Added to library: September 1, 2025

Loading image...
First page of Arthadhigama Chintan

Summary

Here is a comprehensive summary of the Jain text "Arthadhigama Chintan" by Darbarilal Kothiya in English, based on the provided PDF pages:

Arthadhigama Chintan: A Contemplation on the Acquisition of Meaning

This text, "Arthadhigama Chintan" by Darbarilal Kothiya, delves into the fundamental Jain understanding of how we acquire knowledge about reality, particularly focusing on the roles of Pramana (means of valid knowledge) and Naya (partial perspective or standpoint).

The Core of Knowledge Acquisition: Pramana

The author begins by establishing that all Indian philosophical systems agree that Pramana is the sole means of acquiring knowledge about reality (Prameya). Statements like "Pramanam hi Prameyasiddhih" (Knowledge of reality is dependent on valid knowledge) underscore this principle.

However, the Jain perspective distinguishes itself by stating that Pramana is knowledge itself that directly and immediately apprehends the object of knowledge. This is contrasted with other Indian philosophies that often consider sensory activities, the interaction between the knower and the object, or the completeness of sensory organs as Pramana. Jains argue that these external factors are indirect or sequential causes, whereas knowledge is the direct and immediate instrument of understanding. They use the analogy of light dispelling darkness, stating that only knowledge (like light) can remove ignorance, not external activities (like objects).

Two Types of Knowledge Acquisition: Pramana and Naya

Crucially, Jain philosophy introduces Naya as another essential means for acquiring knowledge of objects, alongside Pramana. This duality is first articulated in the Tattvarthasutra. While Pramana provides a comprehensive and undistorted understanding, Naya offers a partial or one-sided perspective.

The Nature of Pramana and its Classification

Jain philosophy categorizes knowledge obtained through Pramana into two types:

  1. Clear (Vishada) or Direct Perception (Pratyaksha): This knowledge does not depend on external factors like senses, mind, or light. It is certain, accurate, and decisive. The three types of such knowledge are:

    • Avadhi: Clairvoyant knowledge.
    • Manahparyaya: Telepathic knowledge.
    • Kevala: Omniscient knowledge. These are considered the primary or ultimate direct perceptions.
  2. Unclear (Avishada) or Indirect Perception (Paroksha): This knowledge relies on external factors like senses, mind, and light. It is only valid to the extent that it aligns with practical, worldly interactions. The two types of such knowledge are:

    • Mati: Sensory and mental knowledge, which includes recollection, recognition, reasoning, inference, and scriptural authority.
    • Shruta: Knowledge derived from scriptures or testimony.

Jains also acknowledge "Saṁvyavahārika Pratyaksha" (practical direct perception) which refers to sensory knowledge (like visual perception) that is commonly understood as direct in the world. However, fundamentally, they are still considered Paroksha due to their reliance on external factors.

Naya: A Partial Aspect of Knowledge

The text then addresses the intricate relationship between Pramana and Naya, posing questions about Naya's nature and its distinction from Pramana. It clarifies that Naya is not an independent means of knowledge, nor is it mere ignorance or incorrect knowledge. Instead, Naya is described as a part or aspect of knowledge, specifically arising from Shruta Pramana.

When a knower or speaker grasps an object by focusing on a particular aspect or feature, either through knowledge or words, that knowledge or utterance is called Naya. When the object is apprehended in its entirety without focusing on any specific aspect, it is considered Pramana.

The text emphasizes that Naya is not an aspect of Mati, Avadhi, or Manahparyaya knowledge because these forms of knowledge are limited in scope. Naya, however, is a decisive apprehension of individual aspects of all objects. While Kevala Jnana apprehends all aspects, it does so directly and completely, not partially and indirectly as Naya does. Therefore, Naya is considered to be exclusively derived from and related to Paroksha Shruta Pramana.

Pramana and Naya: Distinct but Complementary

The author further explains that Naya is neither ignorance nor misinformation. Instead, it is a part of Pramana. This is why it is presented as a separate means of acquiring knowledge. The determination of an object through a specific aspect after its initial apprehension through Pramana is called Naya.

The key difference is that Pramana deals with the whole (Sakalādeśa), while Naya deals with a part (Vikalādeśa). The prominent logician Vidyananda is quoted, using the analogy of a pot of water from the ocean: the water is not the ocean itself, nor is it non-ocean; it is a part of the ocean. Similarly, Naya is a part of Pramana. If Naya were considered the entirety, then the remaining aspects would be considered non-Pramana, leading to an impractical division.

The text asserts that the separate presentation of Naya is essential from the perspective of the limited knower and listener. All worldly dealings and verbal expressions are based on Nayas. The function of Naya is to know or convey individual aspects of an object that possesses infinite qualities. Without Naya, discussions, diverse solutions, debates, and their reconciliation would be impossible. While self-benefiting Pramana is mute and cannot resolve these complexities, Naya possesses this vital capability. Thus, the doctrine of Naya is a significant achievement of Jainism and a unique contribution to Indian philosophy.

The Foundation of Naya: Drvya and Paryaaya

In conclusion, the text reiterates that reality has multiple attributes, and full comprehension cannot be achieved solely through senses or words. Through Nayas, one can grasp individual attributes and, by extension, understand innumerable qualities. When an object is described as substance (Dravya) or modification (Paryaaya), as eternal or impermanent, as one or many, it is always an apprehension or statement of a specific aspect. This kind of apprehension is possible only through Naya, not Pramana.

The renowned Jain logician Siddhasena is cited, stating that for every path of speech, there is a corresponding Naya. Fundamentally, two Nayas are accepted:

  1. Dravyarthika Naya: Grasps substance, generality, and the inherent (anvaya).
  2. Paryayarthika Naya: Grasps modifications, specifics, and the differing aspects (vyatireka).

Both substance and modification together form the object of Pramana. Therefore, Pramana and Naya are two means of acquiring knowledge of reality, and both are effective in their respective domains in apprehending and organizing reality.